The idea of “multiple modernities” has been widely accepted in the discourse on modernity by scholars in various parts of the world. In this paper I want to show the possibility of deriving the idea of multiple democracies from that of “multiple modernities.
1. “Deep-seated reflexivity”: the core of “multiple moderities” as a normative notion
“Multiple modernities” is not only a descriptive notion, but also a normative notion. Even when S. N. Eisenstadt, one of its major advocators, was using it as a descriptive notion, he did not only mean to propose a new description or narrative of the history of modernity, but also meant to argue for the following position: modernization and Westernization are not the same thing.[1] In our times, when the troubles of the Western modernity have been disclosed again and again, to disconnect modernity from “Westernization” is obviously to open a door of hope for those non-Western societies that are in the process of modernization. Looked at in this perspective, Eisenstadt’s notion of “multiple modernity” is already not only descriptive, but also normative, although normative in a negative sense.
In Charles Taylor, another major advocator of the notion of multiple modernities, its normative sense is not merely negative, but also positive.
The need to put forward the problem of modernity in this new way can first of all be understood in a cognitive sense: the impact of particular cultures on modernity is a basic fact, and the admission of the notion of “multiple modernities” is a logical result of the admission of this basic fact, whereas to insist on the acultural theory of modernity, hence to regard modernity as single, is to neglect this basic fact. It can also be understood in an instrumental sense: the project of modernity in non-Western societies would not succeed without being combined with the local cultures in these societies. But neither of these are
This reading of
Recognizing the legitimacy of the “alternative foundations” for norms of conduct, and searching for the “fusion of horizons” of different cultures, requires that one make a critique and reconstruction of one’s own cultural traditions, and be willing to be engaged in dialogues and communications with other cultures. Understood in this way, the notion of “multiple modernities” inherently demands criticism of previous understandings of modernity, searching for new projects of modernity, and learning from other modes of modernity. In short, this is an expression of the self-reflection of modernity. If refusing this kind of self-reflection is not a mere “intellectual error”, then being sincerely ready to have this kind self-reflection is also not merely an intellectual virtue, but an ethical virtue. This, we can say, is the fundamental normative sense of the notion of “multiple modernities”.
It is important to note that this understanding of the normative sense of the idea of multiple modernities is also shared by one of its major advocators: S. N. Eisenstadt. According to Eisenstadt, the cultural and political project called modernity first developed in Western and Middle Europe contains in itself the view of a future characterized by a series of possibilities that can be realized through autonomous human activities. The preconditions for social, ontological and political structures and their legitimation are no longer taken for granted. Around the basic ontological preconditions for the social and political structures of authority there arose a deep-seated reflexivity that is shared even by the most radical opponents of modernity.[10] This kind of reflexivity characteristic of modernity, according to Eisenstadt, goes beyond the reflexivity found in the so-called “axial civilizations”:
The reflexivity that developed in the modern program not only focused on the
possibility of different interpretation of core transcendental visions and basic
ontological conceptions prevalent in a particular society or civilization; it came to
question the very givenness of such visions and the institutional patterns related
to them. It gave rise to an awareness of the possibility of multiple visions that
could, in fact, be contested.[11]
Eisenstadt here uses the term “multiple visions”, which is obviously similar to
2. “Responsible autonomy”: democracy considered in the spirit of the “deep-seated reflexivity”
If we understand the normative core of multiple modernities as a kind of “deep-seated reflexivity”, then, in this epoch of “multiple modernities”, “democracy” can be a subject for deep-seated reflexivity” in the following senses.
Firstly, although democracy has become a major legitimate form of community life in the modern world, we can ask whether it is the only legitimate form of community life in our times. As few of us can deny, even in the most developed democratic societies, democracy is not the only legitimate form of community life. In quite a lot of institutions and communities, such as universities, churches, enterprises, even courts, not to speak of military forces, the democratic form of decision-making plays only a marginal role, if at all. This fact is often referred to by conservatives to argue against democracy as a general form of community life in the society at large. In the spirit of “deep-seated reflexivity”, we should not be afraid of being labeled “conservative” for paying attention to this fact.
Secondly, although democracy has become a major legitimate form of community life in the modern world, we can ask why it is accepted to be so. Democracy, in its essence, is a form of community life in which each member of a community participates in the process of making and implementing the rules that regulate all members of the community, including her/himself. Democracy in this sense is legitimate for two major reasons: it respects each individual’s dignity, because all human individuals are equal and none of them should be placed under any other individual’s rule without his or her consent; it is to each individual’s interest, because the person who knows his or her interest best is this person her/himself, and nobody can speak for this person without his or her authorization. Put these two considerations together and we may say that the essential principle of democracy is the principle of “responsible autonomy”.
Here I would like to make the following additional comments.
It is true that the idea of autonomy, or the idea that the subjects to which the rules of collective actions apply are also their makers, is the only typically modern source of political legitimacy, although it is not necessarily the only actual source of political legitimacy in our times. The major force of the social contract theory in political thinking lies in its ability to provide the most acceptable answer to the person who asks “why I should follow this rule”: “Why not, if you have already agreed to or if you have already taken part in the process of making this rule?”
But the idea of autonomy should not be understood in absolute terms. A person can be seen to be suitable for practicing autonomy only on certain conditions. Not only are persons below a certain age and under certain medical conditions not regarded as being capable of autonomy, but also people who are not specialized in certain fields not regarded to be suitable for making decisions for themselves on issues in these fields. Otherwise they would be practicing their autonomy in an irresponsible way. Democracy, therefore, should not only be based on the principle of autonomy; it should rather be based on the principle of responsible autonomy.
In democratic politics we should not only be responsible to ourselves, but also to our fellow members of the same community; we should not only be responsible to our own particular communities, but also be responsible to human species as a whole. In our times, we have two special challenges, security and sustainability. Both challenges give much more weight to expert knowledge and inter-generational justice, hence to the idea of responsible autonomy. As an example I want to refer to Jürgen Habermas’s recent concern with the dangers of possible democratic legislation for human cloning.
Habermas’s discourse theory of democracy, generally speaking, aims to strengthen the link between autonomy and responsibility, or the link between will and reason. The democratic principle, according to Habermas, “states that only those statues may claim legitimacy that can meet with the assent of all citizens in a discursive process of legislation that in turn has been legally constituted.”[13] Among questions that are to be discussed in the discursive process are moral, ethical and pragmatic questions. In our modern and increasingly complex societies, not only pragmatic questions, but also moral and ethical questions, can be highly complicated, if not technical. A public sphere that is enlightened in Habermas’s sense, therefore, requires for a very important role to be played by experts in various fields as well as philosophers as interpreters and mediators among these fields in addition to mediating between everyday life on the one hand and expert culture on the other.
In his discussion on the issue of human cloning, Habermas continued to rely on his discourse theory of democracy, but seemed to pay more emphasis on responsibility vis-à-vis autonomy. Since the turn of the last century, two major events imposed upon Habermas the same question from different angels: the terrorist attacks of the September 11 of 2001 imposes the problem of the survival of human beings, and the issue of human cloning imposes the problem of the survival of human beings as human beings. Both events are possible partly as a result of the development of modern science. But the second event is possible also as a result of the development of modern democracy. With modern bio-science as an instrument, there is now a danger that a moral community or a liberal democratic community defined in his discourse theory can be self-destroying not only by legislating against its members with regard to what they do (passing a law that limits the freedom of some of its members, for example), but also by legislating against its members and even the whole members of the species with regard to who they and their coming generations will be as human individuals (passing a law that allow human reproduction through human cloning, for example). Facing this kind of challenge, Habermas seems to think it too weak to resort to his discourse theory; in addition to the latter, which is the latest version of secular morality, Habermas now seems to need a defence of the morality of justice and solidarity on the basis of religious traditions, and he does so not only because he needs to appeal to those who believe in religions, but also because he thinks that “only religious language has yet been able to give a sufficiently differentiated expression” to some deeply important moral feelings.[14] For example, human individuals are both equal and autonomous,[15] and some deeds are not only morally wrong but also profoundly evil.[16] What philosophy can do here is try to provide a secular translation of the deep-seated human self-understanding in religion, so that people of other religions as well as secular societies can better understand each other.[17] This may be taken as case in which philosophers play a very important role if democracy is to be practiced in a more responsible way.
3. “Multiple democracies”: “responsible autonomy” under particular national conditions
If the essence of democracy can be understood to be “responsible autonomy”, then, from the idea of “multiple modernities” we can derive the idea of “multiple democracies” for two reasons. On the one hand, if modernity as a whole is deeply entangled with particular cultures in various regions of the world, then democracy as a major element of modernity must be inherently connected to these cultures as well. On the other hand, in the spirit of “deep-seated reflexivity” characteristic of multiple modernities, we can look for the meaning of democracy as a way of practicing “responsible autonomy” under particular national conditions.
Here I want to refer to the work of a Chinese philosopher named Feng Qi (1915-1994). Every moral action, Feng said, should fulfill two principles: the principle of self-consciousness (or the principle of reasonable thinking) and the principle of self-willingness (or the principle of free will). The principle of reasonable thinking is a principle with regard to one’s reason, and the principle of free will is a principle with regard to one’s will. These two principles can be seen as being implied in what I called above the idea of “responsible autonomy”. The reason why I want to refer to Feng Qi is that he made an interesting comparison between Chinese and Western cultures with regard to these two principles. In both cultures, he says, there were thinkers who argued for both principles. Relatively speaking, however, these two principles are given different priorities in Chinese and Western cultures. In
Although Feng Qi here gave us a picture of convergence rather than divergence between Chinese and Western ways of community life, whether it is called democracy or not, we can make use of the two principles just mentioned in discussing the idea of multiple democracies or the multiple forms of practicing “responsible autonomy” under particular national conditions.
Firstly, there can be different ways of realizing the principle of reasonable thinking. The major difference between the life of a community composed of different individuals and the life of the individual in this aspect is, of course, that the decision-making in the former case, or the collective decision-making, depends on the reasonable “thinking together” of individual members of the community, rather than on the reasonable “thinking alone” of one individual or more isolated individuals. That would be the same in the West and in the East. But as soon as we turn our attention to the particular ways of “thinking together” in the process of collective decision-making, we can see that there could be big differences in different cultures. In
Secondly, there can be different ways of realizing the principle of free will. In terms of the procedures of expressing individual wills, we can have procedures in which people express their wills directly or indirectly, through personal participation or through their representatives. People can also express their wills in the process of voting for candidates and draft resolutions or in the process of consultation, and so on. In terms of the personal attitudes of those who are supposed to express their individual wills, we can mention the difference with regard to the level of people’s interest in affairs of one’s communities, and the level of people’s being confident in their own opinions. These differences can result in very different forms of collective decision-making, including democracy.
Finally, there can be different ways in which the principle of reasonable thinking and the principle of free will are combined. As we mentioned above, Feng Qi made a comparison with regard to the different priorities given to these two principles in the Chinese and the Western traditions. On the whole, according to Feng Qi, in the West priority was traditionally given to the principle of free will instead of the principle of reasonable thinking with regard to community life and collective decision-making. That is why in the West the social contract theory has been the most important tradition of democratic thinking and the idea of autonomy or self-rule has been the essential core of the definition of democracy. In
In recent years many efforts have been made in
This paper was published in Multiple Democracies in Theory and History, edited by Simen Andersen Øyen and Rasmus Slaattelid, SVT-Press at the
References
Eisenstadt, S.N.. 2000, “Multiple Modernities”, in Daedalus, Winter, special issue on
Multiple Modernities, pp. 2-3.
Feng Qi. 1997, Revolutionary Process of Modern Chinese Philosophy,
Habermas, Jürgen. 1996, Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse
Theory of Law and Democracy, trans. William Rehg, The MIT Press,
Mass.
---. 2003, The Future of Human Nature, Polity Press,
Taylor, Charles. 1989, Sources of the Self: the Making of the Modernity Identity,
---. 1999, “Two Theories of Modernity”, Public Culture, Vol. 11, Issue 1.
---. 1999, “Conditions of an Unforced Consensus on Human Rights”, in East Asian
Challenge for Human Rights, edited by Joanne R. Bauer and Daniel A. Bell,
Notes:
[1] Eisenstadt, S. N., 2000, pp. 2-3
[2] Taylor, Charles, “Two Theories of Modernity”, 1999, p. 162
[3] Ibid, p. 73
[4] Taylor, Charles, “Conditions of an Unforced Consensus on Human Rights”, 1999, p. 125
[5] Ibid, p. 133
[6] Ibid, p. 124
[7] Taylor, Charles, 1989, p. 515
[8] Ibid, p. 515
[9] Ibid, p. 516
[10] Eisenstadt, S. N., 2000, p. 3
[11] Ibid, p. 4.
[12] Ibid, p. 25
[13] Habermas, Jürgen, 1996, p. 110
[14] See Jürgen Habermas: “Faith and Knowledge”, in Habermas, 2003, p. 114
[15] See Jürgen Habermas: “The Debate on the Ethical Self-Understanding of the Species”, in Habermas, 2003, p. 78
[16] See Jürgen Habermas: “Faith and Knowledge”, in Habermas, 2003, p. 110
[17] See Jürgen Habermas: “Faith and Knowledge”, in Habermas, 2003, p. 114
[18] Feng Qi, 1997, pp. 27-30